Notebook per
Can Our Capacity for Moral Reasoning Be Strengthened?
Citation (APA): Jacobson, D. (2016). Can Our Capacity for Moral Reasoning Be Strengthened? [Kindle Android version]. Retrieved from Amazon.com
Parte introduttiva
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 2
Can Our Capacity for Moral Reasoning Be Strengthened? By Daniel Jacobson
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 6
Recent “scientific” pessimism on this score claims that what we take to be moral reasons are mere rationalizations; and that when we think we are reasoning with others, we are actually engaged in unreasoned persuasion.
Nota - Posizione 7
PESSIMISMO
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 9
This extravagant view treats half-truths about the difficulty of moral reasoning as if they were the whole truth about its impossibility. The case for such strong pessimism rests not on science but scientism:
Nota - Posizione 10
MEZZA VERITÀ TRASFORMATE IN VERITÀ
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 11
In the first place, the human capacity for moral reasoning can be strengthened because our general reasoning capacities are amenable to improvement. This is most readily observed by considering how people develop as they mature from children to adults. We improve at logic, whether or not we learn the fancy Latinate names for rules of inference.
Nota - Posizione 12
È LA RAZIONALITÁ IN GENERE CHE PUÒ ESSERE MIGLIORATA
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 15
inference to the best explanation.
Nota - Posizione 15
x
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 16
If the lawns and streets are wet this morning, the best explanation is that it rained last night while we were asleep.
Nota - Posizione 16
BEST EXP
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 20
First, haven’t behavioral economists and psychologists shown us that people are very bad at reasoning? We humans are predictably irrational
Nota - Posizione 21
L OBIEZIONE COMPORTAMENTISTA
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 22
Second, what do these reflections on general-purpose reasoning have to do with specifically moral thought?
Nota - Posizione 23
2 OB: RAGIONAMENTO E RAG. MORALE SONO COSE DIVERSE
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 23
people unreflectively adopt heuristics— rough-and-ready simplifying principles— that work pretty well in a wide variety of common contexts. When interested parties, including both marketers and scientists, figure out the heuristics people use, they can exploit circumstances where it fails. We commonly chase sunk costs, overvalue things that belong to us, and respond differently to equivalent scenarios depending on how they are framed. Although these failures of rationality are fascinating and important, concentration on them can obscure the fact that our reasoning works well in many other circumstances.
Nota - Posizione 25
LA SCOPERYA COMPORT.
Nota - Posizione 27
c
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 28
Plenty of general reasoning is morally relevant, in that it can be applied to morally significant cases and yield practical conclusions.
Nota - Posizione 29
RAGIONE GENERALE E RAG. MORALE
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 31
Kids learn early that “It’s not fair” is more powerful than “I don’t want to” or just “No.”
Nota - Posizione 32
BAMBINI
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 33
But quickly enough one learns that claims about fairness have to be disciplined in certain ways. You can only make a claim of fairness when you can offer reasons
Nota - Posizione 34
c
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 46
link to one of the most prominent papers in the pessimistic genre,
Nota - Posizione 46
x
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 47
The idea that the human brain is a machine built to win arguments rather than to discover the truth seizes on the fact that people are biased in myriad ways, and these biases influence their evaluation of evidence. (This tendency is not quite as dismal as it seems, since it makes sense to hold on to core beliefs and values firmly rather than continually reevaluating them, which would have significant psychic costs.) But the claim that the brain’s primary function is advocacy rather than discovery is not credible. Most intellectual tasks involve problem solving rather than persuasion; you don’t argue with a bear but hunt, fight, or flee from it. Even in social contexts, where persuasion is most important, there are obvious costs to being proven wrong. Convince the tribe that bears are harmless and your reputation is likely to suffer.
Nota - Posizione 51
CONTRO ADVOCACY: I BIAS HANNO SENSO. CHI NN RISOLVE PROBLEMI MUORE
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 54
The second claim is directed specifically at moral reasoning, which it holds to be mere rationalization.
Nota - Posizione 54
x
Nota - Posizione 54
x
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 57
The strongest case comes from the well-documented human capacity to confabulate about our reasons, telling neat stories about what we do and why, which do not hold up under scrutiny. Although confabulation happens in various contexts, many of which have nothing to do with value judgment, no one thinks that this phenomenon supports a global pessimism about reasons. Even if we sometimes get it wrong about what we’re doing, everyone grants that in most ordinary contexts we know both what we are doing and why. Moreover, sometimes when people confabulate a false causal story, they are still sensitive to reasons that they cannot articulate.
Nota - Posizione 61
PROVA RAZIONALIZZAZIONE: RICOSTRUZIONE ERRATA
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 64
Consider one of the most frequently cited experiments
Nota - Posizione 64
LA PROVA VS LA RAGIONE
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 65
subjects were morally dumbfounded by various “offensive yet harmless” scenarios, such as eating one’s dead pet dog and cleaning the toilet with the flag. That is to say, although they were quite sure there was something wrong with these actions, the subjects could not give reasons
Nota - Posizione 67
HAIDT
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 69
it has serious problems, the worst of which is that it presupposes an extremely narrow conception of what can count as a good practical reason:
Nota - Posizione 70
RAGION PRATICA
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 72
the experimenters stipulate that there are no harmful consequences of actions that stir up strong aversive reactions.
Nota - Posizione 73
STIPULATE
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 73
one cannot simply stipulate that a type of action isn’t dangerous— that is, likely to be harmful in realistic contexts— or that it does not violate well-founded rules, such as the rule laboratories have against the desecration of corpses. The general tendencies of actions are matters of fact rather than stipulation.
Nota - Posizione 75
c
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 77
psychological literature on moral dumbfounding presupposes that the only thing that can count as a practical reason is harm. It then adopts an untenably narrow conception of what counts as harmful that ignores danger, treats well-founded rules as mere suggestions, and ignores painful emotions even when they are predictable.
Nota - Posizione 79
IL DANNO COME HOME UNICO MALE
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 83
There is nothing inherently magical about being averse to sticking pins in a doll constructed to resemble your child, for instance. Magical thinking requires some false causal belief, such as belief in the power of voodoo;
Nota - Posizione 84
WODOO
Nota - Posizione 86
x
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 86
symbol
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 88
While there is a science of disgust, there is no science of the disgusting— that is, of what merits disgust— and the tacit assumption that only germs can be disgusting leads to some obviously absurd conclusions.
Nota - Posizione 90
RIVALUTARE IL DISGUSTO
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 95
Though one could attempt to formulate an empirical notion of what counts as an injury, say, all that would do is demonstrate that there are other sorts of harms than injuries. It is simply not in the purview of science to discover what humans ought to care about.
Nota - Posizione 96
L ERRORE
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 103
the question was not whether moral reasoning is difficult to engage in honestly and, at least sometimes, harder to follow. It was whether it is possible to strengthen our capacity for moral reasoning— or
Nota - Posizione 105
DIFFICILE MA POSSIBILE
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 105
The modestly pessimistic claim is true but rather obvious
Nota - Posizione 106
BANALMENTE VERO
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 115
Discussion Summary
Nota - Posizione 115
T
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 126
The biggest problem with the simple story of moral judgment as expression of emotion is that nobody treats moral judgments— their own or other people’s— in this way.
Nota - Posizione 127
NESSUNO CONSIDERA LA MORALITÀ UN EMOZIO
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 129
Another fact about how moral discourse actually takes place is that we do not simply make judgments but offer reasons for them, which purport to justify those judgments. We do not simply say that abortion is always wrong or permissible (or some more qualified claim).
Nota - Posizione 131
c
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 132
Although many people hold skeptical theories about moral judgment, few can consistently treat moral judgments the way those theories seem to require. And it does seem like some reasons are better than others.
Nota - Posizione 133
INCOERENZA DEI PESSOMISTI
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 135
we treat moral judgments: as claims that stand in need of justification,
Nota - Posizione 135
c
Evidenzia (giallo) - Posizione 139
There are many domains of evaluative judgment— concerning aesthetics, for instance— where it seems clear that something human must be implicated in truths about beauty.
Nota - Posizione 140
GIUDIZIO ESTETICO